Compare commits
4 commits
87777f4e0e
...
d2c948b18b
Author | SHA1 | Date | |
---|---|---|---|
d2c948b18b | |||
a2f5f23749 | |||
ee0f43dd90 | |||
6ddf32c3ef |
4 changed files with 189 additions and 108 deletions
54
work/2024/mes-45/wiki-bios.md
Normal file
54
work/2024/mes-45/wiki-bios.md
Normal file
|
@ -0,0 +1,54 @@
|
||||||
|
# Wiki Bios
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
## Wiki Bio 3
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Shirin Aliabadi 10 March 1973 -> 1 October 2018
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
### biography
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
- Born in Tehran, Iran
|
||||||
|
- Mentored by older borther
|
||||||
|
- Raised in rich environment until Iranian Revolution, went abroad to study art
|
||||||
|
history at University of Paris
|
||||||
|
- Commuted between Paris and Tehran, although primarily based in Tehran
|
||||||
|
- Exhibited worldwide
|
||||||
|
- Art is part of several notable collections (Deutsche Bank in Germany, Bristol
|
||||||
|
City Museum and Art Gallery, Farjam Collection in Dubai)
|
||||||
|
- Passed away in Tehran after battling cancer
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
### artwork
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
- Delves into conflicting influences on young urban Iranian women
|
||||||
|
- Tension between traditional values, religious restrictions, pervasive impact
|
||||||
|
of globalized Western culture
|
||||||
|
- Photographic series _Girls in Cars_, women riding in cars, ready to party
|
||||||
|
- Illustrates contradiction between Iranian restrictions and youthful women
|
||||||
|
who were engaging with Western style traditions
|
||||||
|
- _Operation Supermarket_, criticized failed capitalism and consumerism
|
||||||
|
- Common household goods to question and critique societal values and
|
||||||
|
economic systems
|
||||||
|
- _Miss Hybrid_ presents young Iranian women in unconventional and striking
|
||||||
|
ways, features women with bleached blonde hair, blue contacts, flawless
|
||||||
|
makeup, in contrast with traditional view of Muslim women.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
### bio
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Shirin Aliabadi was a contemporary Iranian artist. Born on March 10th, 1973 in
|
||||||
|
Tehran, Iran, she was exposed to a rich environment of art and culture while
|
||||||
|
growing up, until the Iranian Revolution left both of her parents jobless.
|
||||||
|
However, they still managed to send her overseas where she obtained a degree in
|
||||||
|
art history at the University of Paris.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Aliabadi was primarily based in Tehran but frequently commuted to Paris. Her
|
||||||
|
artwork spans both photographs and drawings and has been exhibited worldwide,
|
||||||
|
including in collections in Germany, Dubai, and France. A prevalent theme in
|
||||||
|
her artwork is the contrast between the traditional view held in the West of
|
||||||
|
muslim women and the reality around her in Iran. Her most famous works, _Girls
|
||||||
|
in Cars_, and _Miss Hybrid_, both portrayed Iranian women in unconventional
|
||||||
|
ways that were in contradiction with the traditional culture and values muslim
|
||||||
|
women are often associated with. Women were depicted with bleached blonde hair,
|
||||||
|
flawless makeup, and heading to parties in cars. Aliabadi's artwork highlighted
|
||||||
|
the social and cultural structures in Iranian society and the shifts happening
|
||||||
|
alongside the proliferation of Western culture.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Aliabadi passed away in 2018 at the age of 45 after battling cancer.
|
Binary file not shown.
|
@ -8,12 +8,25 @@
|
||||||
bibliography: bibliography("refs.bib"),
|
bibliography: bibliography("refs.bib"),
|
||||||
)
|
)
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
#show: word-count.with(exclude: (heading, <wordcount-exclude>, table))
|
#show: word-count.with(exclude: (
|
||||||
|
heading,
|
||||||
|
<wordcount-exclude>,
|
||||||
|
table,
|
||||||
|
figure,
|
||||||
|
footnote,
|
||||||
|
))
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
#set cite(style: "institute-of-electrical-and-electronics-engineers")
|
||||||
|
#set text(fractions: true)
|
||||||
|
#set table(inset: 8pt, align: center)
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
#align(
|
#align(
|
||||||
center,
|
center,
|
||||||
|
pad(
|
||||||
|
x: 20%,
|
||||||
table(
|
table(
|
||||||
columns: (auto, auto),
|
columns: (1fr, 1fr),
|
||||||
[
|
[
|
||||||
Perm: A2V4847
|
Perm: A2V4847
|
||||||
],
|
],
|
||||||
|
@ -22,20 +35,21 @@
|
||||||
#footnote[
|
#footnote[
|
||||||
Figure computed programmatically during document compilation. Discounts
|
Figure computed programmatically during document compilation. Discounts
|
||||||
content in tables and the AI contribution statement.
|
content in tables and the AI contribution statement.
|
||||||
]<wordcount-exclude>
|
]
|
||||||
],
|
],
|
||||||
),
|
),
|
||||||
|
),
|
||||||
)
|
)
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
= Introduction
|
= Introduction
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
The argument for Betting on God says that you should believe in God, regardless
|
The argument for Betting on God says that you should believe in God, regardless
|
||||||
of other evidence, purely out of self-interest. In this paper, I challenge this
|
of other evidence, purely out of rational self-interest. In this paper, I
|
||||||
argument by assessing the premise that believing in a particular God always
|
challenge this argument by assessing the premise that believing in a particular
|
||||||
guarantees the greatest expected utility.
|
God always guarantees the greatest expected utility.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
The author's argument for belief in God #cite(supplement: [p. 38],
|
The author's argument for belief in God on #cite(supplement: [p. 38],
|
||||||
<Korman2022-KORLFA>) goes as follows:
|
<Korman2022-KORLFA>) goes as follows:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
#indented-argument(
|
#indented-argument(
|
||||||
|
@ -46,21 +60,29 @@ The author's argument for belief in God #cite(supplement: [p. 38],
|
||||||
[So, you should believe in God.],
|
[So, you should believe in God.],
|
||||||
)
|
)
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
BG1 should be uncontroversial. If you expect an action to bring you the most
|
BG1 should be uncontroversial. If you expect that an action will bring you the
|
||||||
utility (i.e. be the most useful), it's rational to do it.
|
most utility (i.e. be the most useful), it's rational to choose to do it.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
// To justify BG2, the author uses a so-called "decision matrix" to compute the
|
||||||
|
// expected utility of each combination of action and possible outcome. The
|
||||||
|
// possible actions are placed on the rows, and the possible outcomes are placed
|
||||||
|
// on the columns, except for the last column, which is the calculated expected
|
||||||
|
// utility. At each intersection of a row and column, we place the utility gained
|
||||||
|
// from that combination of action and outcome. The expected utility for a given
|
||||||
|
// action is computed by multiplying the utility of each action-outcome pair in
|
||||||
|
// that action's row by the probability of the corresponding outcome occurring,
|
||||||
|
// and summing up all of those values.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
To justify BG2, the author uses a so-called "decision matrix" to compute the
|
To justify BG2, the author uses a so-called "decision matrix" to compute the
|
||||||
expected utility of each combination of action and possible outcome. The
|
expected utility of either belief or disbelief in God. Both possible actions
|
||||||
possible actions are placed on the rows, and the possible outcomes are placed
|
are placed on the first column, and the possible outcomes (God existing or God
|
||||||
on the columns, except for the last column, which is the calculated expected
|
not existing) are placed on the first row. The last column of the matrix
|
||||||
utility. At each intersection of a row and column, we place the utility we gain
|
represents the expected utility of the action in its corresponding row. At each
|
||||||
from that combination of action and outcome. The expected utility for a given
|
intersection of action and outcome, we write the utility gained from that
|
||||||
action is computed by multiplying the utility of each action-outcome pair in
|
action-outcome combination.
|
||||||
that row by the probability of the corresponding outcome occurring, and summing
|
|
||||||
up all of those values.
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Here is the decision matrix the author proposes on #cite(supplement: [p. 38],
|
Here is the decision matrix the author proposes on #cite(supplement: [p. 38],
|
||||||
<Korman2022-KORLFA>) which gives the expected utility for believing or not
|
<Korman2022-KORLFA>) which gives the expected utilities for believing or not
|
||||||
believing in God.
|
believing in God.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
#show table.cell.where(x: 0): strong
|
#show table.cell.where(x: 0): strong
|
||||||
|
@ -90,51 +112,59 @@ believing in God.
|
||||||
),
|
),
|
||||||
)
|
)
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Note that the numerical utility values themselves have no meaning, and they are
|
Note that utility doesn't provide an empirical measure of "usefulness" or
|
||||||
meant to be viewed relative to each other. Utility doesn't literally provide an
|
"happiness," and should be viewed as a relative measurement.
|
||||||
empirical measure of "usefulness" or "happiness."
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
We assign the various finite utilities as we see fit, based on how much each
|
We assign each action-outcome combination utilities as we see fit, based on how
|
||||||
scenario benefits us. In the case where God does exist, and you believed in
|
much each scenario benefits us. You'll see shortly that the exact values we set
|
||||||
God, then you are rewarded with an eternal afterlife of bliss and pleasure in
|
for the finite utilities don't matter when infinite utility is introduced.
|
||||||
heaven. This reward is infinitely greater than any possible reward on earth, so
|
|
||||||
it has a utility of $infinity$.
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
So, the expected utility for not believing is $0.5 times 1 + 0.5 times 3 = 2$,
|
In the specific case where God does exist, and you believed in God, you
|
||||||
and the expected utility is $0.5 times infinity + 0.5 times 2 = infinity$. If,
|
are rewarded with an eternal afterlife of bliss and pleasure in heaven. This
|
||||||
according to BG1, you should pick the option with greatest expected utility,
|
reward is infinitely greater than any possible reward on earth, so it has a
|
||||||
clearly you should choose to believe in God, because the expected utility is
|
utility of $infinity$.
|
||||||
$infinity$.
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
The exact utilities don't matter much, since any finite utility you could gain
|
|
||||||
for atheism cannot possibly be greater than the infinite expected utility of
|
To calculate the expected utility of a given action, we first multiply the
|
||||||
believing in God. Also, as the author points out on #cite(<Korman2022-KORLFA>,
|
utility gained from each action-outcome combination in the action's row by the
|
||||||
supplement: [p. 40]), the exact probabilities don't matter either since
|
probability of the corresponding outcome occurring. We then sum up all of these
|
||||||
multiplying them by $infinity$ still results in the expected utility of
|
values to obtain the final expected utility.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
So, the expected utility for disbelief is $0.5 times 1 + 0.5 times 3 = 2$, and
|
||||||
|
the expected utility for belief is $0.5 times infinity + 0.5 times 2 =
|
||||||
|
infinity$. If, according to BG1, you should pick the option with greatest
|
||||||
|
expected utility, you should clearly choose to believe in God, because the
|
||||||
|
expected utility is $infinity$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Also, as the author points out on #cite(<Korman2022-KORLFA>, supplement: [p.
|
||||||
|
40]), the exact probabilities don't matter either since multiplying even the
|
||||||
|
smallest percentage by $infinity$ still results in the expected utility of
|
||||||
$infinity$.
|
$infinity$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
I will show that the Argument for Betting on God fails because BG2 fails. In
|
I will show that the Argument for Betting on God fails because BG2 fails. In
|
||||||
section 2, I argue you cannot determine whether or not believing in God has the
|
section 2, I argue you cannot determine whether or not believing in God has the
|
||||||
greatest expected utility because the decision matrix approach fails when
|
greatest expected utility because the decision matrix approach fails when
|
||||||
possible outcomes involving infinitely negative utilities are introduced. In
|
possible outcomes involving infinitely negative utilities are introduced. In
|
||||||
section 3, I address a possible response to this objection.
|
section 3, I address a few possible responses to this objection.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
= Possibility of Infinite Suffering
|
= Possibility of Infinite Suffering
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
It is possible there are more gods than just the one that sends you to an
|
I propose that there is the possibility of more gods than just the Christian one that
|
||||||
eternal afterlife for believing? The author partially addresses this in
|
sends you to an eternal afterlife for believing. The author partially addresses
|
||||||
#cite(<Korman2022-KORLFA>, supplement: [pp. 43-44]), using the example of Zeus.
|
this concern on #cite(<Korman2022-KORLFA>, supplement: [pp. 43-44]), using the
|
||||||
Zeus will only reward those who believe in him with an eternal afterlife of
|
example of Zeus. Zeus will only reward those who believe in him specifically
|
||||||
pleasure. So, if you believe in the wrong god, you don't go to the afterlife.
|
with an eternal afterlife. So, if you believe in the wrong god, you don't go to
|
||||||
The author concludes either believing in Zeus or the Christian God still has
|
the afterlife. The author concludes believing in either Zeus or the Christian
|
||||||
expected utilities of $infinity$, while being an atheist does has a finite
|
God still result in expected utilities of $infinity$, while being an atheist
|
||||||
expected utility. Therefore, it is still preferable to believe in _some_ god
|
always has a finite expected utility. Therefore, you should still believe in
|
||||||
that may grant you an eternal afterlife, although no argument is made for
|
_some_ god that could grant you an eternal afterlife, although no argument is
|
||||||
_which_ god.
|
made for _which_ god.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
However, this leaves out the possibility of gods who punish you for some
|
However, this leaves out the possibility of gods who instead punish you for
|
||||||
reason. For instance, suppose there exists an _Evil God_ who sends anyone who
|
eternity. For instance, suppose there exists an _Evil God_ who sends any theist
|
||||||
believes in any god to hell for eternity, and does nothing to atheists.
|
to hell for eternity, and does nothing to atheists. That is, the Evil God will
|
||||||
|
punish anyone who believes in _any_ god, including those who believe in the
|
||||||
|
Evil God themselves.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Let us modify our decision matrix to model an outcome where the Evil God
|
Let us modify our decision matrix to model an outcome where the Evil God
|
||||||
exists.
|
exists.
|
||||||
|
@ -151,7 +181,7 @@ exists.
|
||||||
table.header(
|
table.header(
|
||||||
[],
|
[],
|
||||||
[Correct god exists ($33.3%$)],
|
[Correct god exists ($33.3%$)],
|
||||||
[No god exists ($33.3%$)],
|
[No god or wrong god ($33.3%$)],
|
||||||
[Evil God exists ($33.3%$)],
|
[Evil God exists ($33.3%$)],
|
||||||
[E.U.],
|
[E.U.],
|
||||||
),
|
),
|
||||||
|
@ -172,19 +202,18 @@ We've added the new option to our matrix. For the sake of argument, let's say
|
||||||
each option has an equally likely outcome. Again, the exact probabilities don't
|
each option has an equally likely outcome. Again, the exact probabilities don't
|
||||||
really matter when we're multiplying them by infinity.
|
really matter when we're multiplying them by infinity.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
The utilities are mostly the same as before. Not believing in any god and the
|
The utilities are mostly the same as before. However, the theist now faces the
|
||||||
Evil God existing is now the best case for the atheist since they avoided
|
possibility of the worst case of all: eternal punishment if the Evil God
|
||||||
infinite suffering. However, the theist now faces the possibility of the worst
|
exists. If eternal bliss in heaven has a utility of $infinity$, then it follows
|
||||||
case of all: eternal punishment for believing in the wrong god. If eternal
|
that we should represent eternal punishment in hell with a utility of
|
||||||
bliss in heaven has a utility of $infinity$, then it follows that we should
|
$-infinity$.
|
||||||
represent eternal punishment in hell with a utility of $-infinity$.
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
There is a problem: how do we calculate the expected utility of believing in
|
Let us attempt to calculate the expected utility of believing in god using our
|
||||||
god? We have $0.333 times infinity + 0.333 times 1 + 0.333 times -infinity$.
|
usual method. We have $0.333 times infinity + 0.333 times 1 + 0.333 times
|
||||||
What is $infinity - infinity$? A naive answer might be 0, but infinity is not a
|
-infinity$. What is $infinity - infinity$? A naive answer might be 0, but
|
||||||
number in the traditional sense. It makes no sense to add or subtract infinite
|
infinity is not a number in the traditional sense. It makes no sense to add or
|
||||||
values. For instance, try and subtract the total amount of integers
|
subtract infinite values. For instance, try and subtract the total amount of
|
||||||
($infinity$) from the total amount of real numbers (also $infinity$)
|
integers ($infinity$) from the total amount of real numbers (also $infinity$)
|
||||||
#footnote[Famously, this infinity is "larger" than the infinite number of
|
#footnote[Famously, this infinity is "larger" than the infinite number of
|
||||||
integers in the sense of cardinality (G. Cantor). But subtracting them still
|
integers in the sense of cardinality (G. Cantor). But subtracting them still
|
||||||
makes no mathematical or physical sense.]. Clearly, this notion is meaningless
|
makes no mathematical or physical sense.]. Clearly, this notion is meaningless
|
||||||
|
@ -197,13 +226,13 @@ Consider the following Indeterminate Utilities argument:
|
||||||
title: "The Indeterminate Utilities argument",
|
title: "The Indeterminate Utilities argument",
|
||||||
abbreviation: "IU",
|
abbreviation: "IU",
|
||||||
[If the expected utility of believing in god is undefined, then we
|
[If the expected utility of believing in god is undefined, then we
|
||||||
cannot compare the expected utilities of believing in god or not believing
|
cannot compare the expected utilities of believing in god and not believing
|
||||||
in god.],
|
in god.],
|
||||||
[The expected utility of believing in god is undefined.],
|
[The expected utility of believing in god is undefined.],
|
||||||
[So, we cannot compare the expected utilities of believing in god or
|
[So, we cannot compare the expected utilities of believing in god and
|
||||||
not believing in god.
|
not believing in god.
|
||||||
],
|
],
|
||||||
[If we cannot compare the expected utilities of believing in god or
|
[If we cannot compare the expected utilities of believing in god and
|
||||||
not believing in god, then we cannot determine if believing in god has a
|
not believing in god, then we cannot determine if believing in god has a
|
||||||
higher expected utility than not believing in god.
|
higher expected utility than not believing in god.
|
||||||
],
|
],
|
||||||
|
@ -247,26 +276,26 @@ utility, it is a false premise.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
One might argue that it is not plausible there is an Evil God who punishes all
|
One might argue that it is not plausible there is an Evil God who punishes all
|
||||||
theists, including their own believers. Many religions present a god that
|
theists, including their own believers. Many religions present a god that
|
||||||
rewards believers and at most punishes disbelievers. None of the major world
|
rewards believers and at most punishes disbelievers, yet none of the major
|
||||||
religions propose an Evil God who punishes all believers. It's much more likely
|
world religions propose an Evil God who punishes all believers
|
||||||
that a benevolent god exists than an evil one.
|
indiscriminately. It's much more likely that a benevolent god exists than an
|
||||||
|
evil one.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
I contend that it doesn't matter whether or not the Evil God is less plausible
|
Notice that it doesn't actually matter how plausible the Evil God is. If a
|
||||||
than a benevolent god. Surely, if a rational atheist who is unconvinced by all
|
rational atheist should concede there is at least a non-zero chance some god
|
||||||
the world's scriptures can still concede that there is at least a non-zero
|
exists, then there must also be a non-zero chance the Evil God exists. After
|
||||||
chance that some god exists, the rational theist should also concede that there
|
all, can you say for sure that the Evil God doesn't exist? All it takes is that
|
||||||
is a non-zero chance that the Evil God exists. All it takes is that non-zero
|
non-zero chance, no matter how small, because multiplying it by $-infinity$
|
||||||
chance, no matter how small, because multiplying it by $-infinity$ still
|
still results in the undefined expected utility.
|
||||||
results in the undefined expected utility.
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
== Finite utilities
|
== Finite utilities
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
One might argue that we can avoid using $infinity$ to ensure that all expected
|
One might argue that we can avoid using $infinity$ to ensure that all expected
|
||||||
utility calculations are defined. Instead, suppose that the utility of going to
|
utility calculations are defined. Instead, suppose the utility of going to
|
||||||
heaven is just an immensely large finite number. The utility of going to hell
|
heaven is just an immensely large finite number. The utility of going to hell
|
||||||
is likewise a very negative number. All of our expected utility calculations
|
is likewise a very negative number. All of our expected utility calculations
|
||||||
will be defined, and given sufficiently large utilities, we should be able to
|
will be defined, since infinity is not used. Given sufficiently large
|
||||||
make a similar argument for believing in god.
|
utilities, we should be able to make a similar argument for believing in god.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
// The problem with this argument is that we now open our expected utilities up to
|
// The problem with this argument is that we now open our expected utilities up to
|
||||||
// individual subjective determination. A core feature of the previous argument
|
// individual subjective determination. A core feature of the previous argument
|
||||||
|
@ -277,21 +306,24 @@ make a similar argument for believing in god.
|
||||||
// well. This greatly complicates the decision matrix.
|
// well. This greatly complicates the decision matrix.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
The problem with this argument is that infinity has a special property the
|
The problem with this argument is that infinity has a special property the
|
||||||
argument relies on. Namely, any number multiplied by $infinity$ is still
|
argument relies on that no finite numbers have. Namely, any number multiplied
|
||||||
$infinity$, so the exact probabilities we set for the existence of God don't
|
by $infinity$ is still $infinity$, so the exact probabilities we set for the
|
||||||
matter. This is important for defending against the objection the author
|
existence of God don't matter. This is important for defending against the
|
||||||
mentions on #cite(<Korman2022-KORLFA>, supplement: [p. 40]), that the
|
objection that the probabilities are possibly incorrect which the author
|
||||||
probabilities are possibly incorrect, since the numbers don't matter anyways.
|
mentions on #cite(<Korman2022-KORLFA>, supplement: [p. 40]). If the exact
|
||||||
|
numbers don't matter due to $infinity$, it doesn't matter if they might be
|
||||||
|
wrong (as long as they are non-zero).
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
If, instead, only finite utilities were used, then the theist must contend with
|
If, instead, only finite utilities were used, the concern that the
|
||||||
the concern that the probabilities in the matrix are wrong. There could
|
probabilities in the matrix are wrong cannot be resolved with the same argument
|
||||||
conceivably exist a matrix with probabilities for a benevolent god and an Evil
|
as before. There could conceivably exist a matrix with probabilities for a
|
||||||
God such that the expected utility of atheism is actually higher. The issue is
|
benevolent god and an Evil God such that the expected utility of atheism is
|
||||||
we cannot say for sure what the probabilities of the benevolent god and the
|
actually higher. The issue is we cannot say for sure what the probabilities of
|
||||||
Evil God existing are. If we cannot know what the actual probabilities are,
|
the benevolent god and the Evil God existing are. If we cannot know what the
|
||||||
then we cannot know the final outcome of our matrix. So, without knowing the
|
actual probabilities are, then we cannot know the final outcome of our matrix.
|
||||||
final outcome of the matrix, we still cannot determine whether or not believing
|
So, without knowing the final outcome of the matrix, we still cannot determine
|
||||||
in god has greater expected utility, and BG2 still fails.
|
whether or not believing in god has greater expected utility, and BG2 still
|
||||||
|
fails.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
#pagebreak()
|
#pagebreak()
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -1,6 +1,3 @@
|
||||||
#set cite(style: "institute-of-electrical-and-electronics-engineers")
|
|
||||||
#set text(fractions: true)
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
#let indented-argument(title: "", abbreviation: "", ..args) = [
|
#let indented-argument(title: "", abbreviation: "", ..args) = [
|
||||||
#set par(first-line-indent: 0pt)
|
#set par(first-line-indent: 0pt)
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
@ -17,5 +14,3 @@
|
||||||
..args.pos(),
|
..args.pos(),
|
||||||
)
|
)
|
||||||
]
|
]
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue