Compare commits
4 commits
71387e82e1
...
c8229c56b8
Author | SHA1 | Date | |
---|---|---|---|
c8229c56b8 | |||
d1fdc85cc6 | |||
f2aea5c16c | |||
a116444068 |
6 changed files with 151 additions and 8 deletions
1
.gitignore
vendored
1
.gitignore
vendored
|
@ -1 +1,2 @@
|
||||||
result
|
result
|
||||||
|
main.pdf
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -0,0 +1,35 @@
|
||||||
|
{
|
||||||
|
pkgs,
|
||||||
|
typstPackagesCache,
|
||||||
|
typixLib,
|
||||||
|
cleanTypstSource,
|
||||||
|
...
|
||||||
|
}:
|
||||||
|
let
|
||||||
|
src = cleanTypstSource ./.;
|
||||||
|
commonArgs = {
|
||||||
|
typstSource = "main.typ";
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
fontPaths = [
|
||||||
|
# Add paths to fonts here
|
||||||
|
# "${pkgs.roboto}/share/fonts/truetype"
|
||||||
|
];
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
virtualPaths = [
|
||||||
|
# Add paths that must be locally accessible to typst here
|
||||||
|
# {
|
||||||
|
# dest = "icons";
|
||||||
|
# src = "${inputs.font-awesome}/svgs/regular";
|
||||||
|
# }
|
||||||
|
];
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
XDG_CACHE_HOME = typstPackagesCache;
|
||||||
|
};
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
in
|
||||||
|
typixLib.buildTypstProject (
|
||||||
|
commonArgs
|
||||||
|
// {
|
||||||
|
inherit src;
|
||||||
|
}
|
||||||
|
)
|
Binary file not shown.
Binary file not shown.
Binary file not shown.
|
@ -43,9 +43,13 @@
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
= Introduction
|
= Introduction
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
The argument Against Fearing Death proposes the surprising thesis that you
|
The argument Against Fearing Death says that you should not fear being dead
|
||||||
should not fear being dead because it is not bad for you. The author states it
|
because it is not bad for you. In this paper, I reject this thesis by showing
|
||||||
as follows on #cite(<Korman2022-KORLFA>, supplement: [p. 74]):
|
that the argument from hedonism with which the author supports their premises
|
||||||
|
forces us to draw incorrect conclusions.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
The author states the argument against fearing death as follows on
|
||||||
|
#cite(<Korman2022-KORLFA>, supplement: [p. 74]):
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
#indented-argument(
|
#indented-argument(
|
||||||
title: "Against Fearing Death",
|
title: "Against Fearing Death",
|
||||||
|
@ -57,22 +61,125 @@ as follows on #cite(<Korman2022-KORLFA>, supplement: [p. 74]):
|
||||||
[ So, you should not fear death ],
|
[ So, you should not fear death ],
|
||||||
)
|
)
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
To support premise FD2, the author argues
|
First off, the author does not argue that you should not fear the _process_ of
|
||||||
|
dying. A painful death is something to be rationally feared. The author only
|
||||||
|
argues that _being dead_ itself is not bad. That is, you may fear the way by
|
||||||
|
which you die, but you should not fear the state of being dead itself.
|
||||||
|
Furthermore, if there was a high likelihood you may die painlessly, perhaps
|
||||||
|
under anesthesia during a risky surgery, you should not fear that either, as
|
||||||
|
you will painlessly transition from being alive to being dead, and there is
|
||||||
|
nothing to fear about being dead.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
The author justifies FD1 by denying the only possibility of rejecting it, which
|
||||||
|
is the notion that your consciousness continues after the death of your
|
||||||
|
physical body, perhaps in an afterlife. He rejects this idea by arguing that
|
||||||
|
you, the consciousness reading this, and your physical human body, are one and
|
||||||
|
the same (i.e. they are _numerically equivalent_). So, if your physical human
|
||||||
|
body biologically ceases to be conscious after death (which it does), then you
|
||||||
|
also cease to be conscious when you die.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Premise FD3 is the direct result of FD1 and FD2, so its validity is dependent
|
||||||
|
entirely on FD1 and FD2. We've already shown why FD1 should be accepted. Let us
|
||||||
|
first examine FD4 before returning to FD2.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
FD4 makes a lot of intuitive sense. Indeed, upon close inspection, there are no
|
||||||
|
glaring issues. It is rational to fear something if and only if it is bad for
|
||||||
|
you. Sure, you may fear things that are not bad for you, but these fears are
|
||||||
|
_irrational_, you should try to resist them. The only things that it is
|
||||||
|
rational to fear are things that are actually bad for you, such as burning your
|
||||||
|
hand on a hot stove, or stubbing your toe.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Finally, we return to premise FD2. This is perhaps the most questionable
|
||||||
|
premise as it is not immediately clear why being unconscious implies that being
|
||||||
|
dead is not bad.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
We first need a rigorous account of what exactly characterizes something as
|
||||||
|
"bad." The author defines the following hedonist principle:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
#pad(
|
||||||
|
left: 16pt,
|
||||||
|
[ (HD\*) Something is bad for you if and only if it results in
|
||||||
|
more pain than you would otherwise have had ],
|
||||||
|
)
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Then, he constructs the following #smallcaps[Argument from Hedonism] to support
|
||||||
|
FD2.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
#indented-argument(
|
||||||
|
title: "The Argument from Hedonism",
|
||||||
|
abbreviation: "AH",
|
||||||
|
[
|
||||||
|
If you cease to be conscious when you die, then being dead doesn't result in more pain than you otherwise would have had
|
||||||
|
],
|
||||||
|
[
|
||||||
|
Something is bad for you if and only if it results in more pain than you otherwise would have had
|
||||||
|
],
|
||||||
|
[
|
||||||
|
$<==>$ (FD2) So, if you cease to be conscious when you die, then being dead isn't bad for you
|
||||||
|
],
|
||||||
|
)
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
I've slightly modified the author's numberings to emphasize that the conclusion
|
||||||
|
AH3 is equivalent to the premise FD2. That is, if the #smallcaps[Argument from
|
||||||
|
Hedonism] holds, then FD2 must be true.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
We've shown that the author's argument for why you should not fear death is
|
||||||
|
substantiated by what appear to be valid premises. I object in section 2 by
|
||||||
|
arguing that we should _not_ accept the author's hedonist principle, and
|
||||||
|
therefore should not accept premise FD2, because it leads us to the conclusion
|
||||||
|
that we should kill ourselves. In section 3, I address various potential
|
||||||
|
responses to my objection.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
= Don't kill yourself
|
= Don't kill yourself
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
I will advance the argument that we should reject HD\* because its logical
|
||||||
|
conclusion is that you should kill yourself. HD\* implies that being dead is
|
||||||
|
not bad for you, but it also implies that _being alive_ is bad for you.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
#indented-argument(
|
#indented-argument(
|
||||||
title: "Argument for Killing Yourself",
|
title: "Argument for Killing Yourself",
|
||||||
abbreviation: "KYS",
|
abbreviation: "KYS",
|
||||||
[You are conscious when you are alive],
|
[You are occasionally conscious when you are alive],
|
||||||
[Something is bad for you if and only if it results in more pain than you otherwise would have had],
|
|
||||||
[If you are conscious, you experience more pain than you otherwise would have if you were unconscious],
|
[If you are conscious, you experience more pain than you otherwise would have if you were unconscious],
|
||||||
|
[$<==>$ (HD\*) Something is bad for you if and only if it results in more pain than you otherwise would have had],
|
||||||
[So, being alive is bad for you],
|
[So, being alive is bad for you],
|
||||||
[If you are unconscious when you are dead, then being dead isn't bad for you],
|
[If you are unconscious when you are dead, then being dead isn't bad for you],
|
||||||
[If being alive is bad for you, then: if being dead isn't bad for you, you should kill yourself],
|
[If being alive is bad for you, then: if being dead isn't bad for you, you should stop being alive],
|
||||||
[So, you should kill yourself],
|
[So, you should stop being alive],
|
||||||
)
|
)
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
In other words, KYS7 plainly states that you should kill yourself to stop being
|
||||||
|
alive. This is clearly a ridiculous conclusion and one we should not accept. In
|
||||||
|
order to reject this conclusion, we must reject KYS3, which is HD\*. All of the
|
||||||
|
other premises can be substantiated easily, as follows.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
KYS1 is trivial. KYS2 is true because you experience no pain when unconscious,
|
||||||
|
and we certainly experience pain at some point while conscious. So, we must
|
||||||
|
experience more pain while conscious than we otherwise would have (while
|
||||||
|
unconscious).
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
KYS6 essentially just says that if being alive is bad and being dead is good,
|
||||||
|
then you should take action to stop being alive and start being dead. After
|
||||||
|
all, why continue doing something that is bad for you when the alternative not
|
||||||
|
bad for you?
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Clearly, our own avenue forward is to reject HD\* as our principle of hedonism.
|
||||||
|
Without HD\*, the #smallcaps[Argument from Hedonism] no longer stands, and
|
||||||
|
therefore the argument for FD2 fails.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
= Possible objections
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
One might attempt to object to KYS without rejecting HD\*. The only other
|
||||||
|
premises to object against are KYS1 and KYS2. In particular, one might raise
|
||||||
|
the concern that someone could be alive without ever being conscious (as an
|
||||||
|
objection to KYS1), and that someone may not experience any pain while
|
||||||
|
conscious (an objection to KYS2).
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
These criticisms are not substantial enough for us to reject KYS. KYS1 brings
|
||||||
|
up a valid point, but being unconscious for the rest of your life is not really
|
||||||
|
substantially different from being dead. Regardless, we could modify our
|
||||||
|
argument to
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
#pagebreak()
|
#pagebreak()
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
#[
|
#[
|
||||||
|
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue